3 Individual
Individual
Individual as a political sociological category
The previous chapter looked at how political sociologists engage in denaturalization of everyday categories and place them in historically specific socio-political contexts. In this chapter, this approach will be applied to one of the most problematic categories of social analysis, namely, the individual.
While sociology began demarcating its field of study in the foundational works of Émile Durkheim by distinguishing itself from psychology and individualistic explanations of social phenomena, it nevertheless also made constant recourse to individualism as a modern current responsible for a number of social ailments (Durkheim 1997, 2005). Early sociologists emphasized the power of social norms over mental processes in shaping the individual’s behavior. The externality of social facts to individual existence lays bare coercive character of the social, and therefore their inherently political character (Durkheim, 1982). Involving both formal and informal mechanisms of sanctioning (e.g., imprisonment, excommunication, shaming, banishing, and so on) social relations are permanently pregnant with potential scenes of regulation.
Politicizing the category of individual
Explore the ways in which social factors 1) limit and 2) enable individual freedom.
- First, describe an individual by determining their sociological position. Specify where are they in the political cartography of the world (Which country are they living in ? Are they a citizen of the country they are currently inhabiting?) When are they living in history (What technologies and knowledge are available to them, what events are likely to occur? What’s their socio-economic class and status?
- Secondly, list the number of rules, regulations, expectations and ideas that they have to reckon with. What forces that these social facts have on your individual?
- Thirdly, imagine scenarios whereby the individual tries to overcome their social conditions? Discuss whether social conditions are only limitations or can also function as potential openings.
The ability to claim the status of the normal and apply the stigma of the abnormality on select populations then constitutes the goal of ongoing political dramas based on social performances (Goffman, 1959, 1963; Foucault, 2003). Yet, collapsing abstract determination of social facts with its concrete manifestation in typical institutions of its time such as state, family, trends and conventions, early sociologists operated with conservative assumptions that reinforced normality of inherited social formations. More than a century ago, one of the founding figures of modern philosophy of individual experience, Immanuel Kant, refuted this bias towards past as a constitutive erasure of human freedom, which he saw as the condition of possibility of truly moral action (Kant, 1781/2009, p. 398). In opposition to its glorification as the ground that allows emancipation of human freedom and rationality from its enchainment to social conventions and dogmas solidified by communal forces of sanctioning, Durkheim diagnosed an extreme form individualism, namely, atomism the progenitor of modern experience of alienation and anomie that proliferates in the absence of social bonds kept through recurrent social rituals.
Thus, while being rejected as a unit of analysis to ground sociological method, the individual played a significant role in the formation of sociological discourse and its political reading of the modern condition. The problematic of the individual demonstrates how political sociology weaves together a trans-disciplinary field. Inhabiting this problematic zone, the figure of individual provides a fertile ground to introduce major themes of political sociology and its critical attitude that underpins its work of denaturalizing givens of social experience.
Critique of the individual
From philosophic critique to political economic critique
When Immanuel Kant wrote his critique of pure reason, he explored conditions of possibility of experience. He discovered that in order to organize myriad sensory stimuli into meaningful perceptions, subjects must be already equipped with some analytical tools, namely, notions that would allow us to configure what disparately takes place in space and time (e.g., causality). Accordingly, causality is not an intrinsic quality of objects; it is the human rational organization of sensory data that discovers/projects a causality within/onto what’s otherwise a mere succession of occurrences. With this approach, he paved the way for the modern theoretical enterprise called critique. Critique as a research methodology involves the uncovering of necessary assumptions that one can extract from what presents itself as evidently true. Following Kant, scholars from different disciplines argued for many more elements to be necessary for an individual to have a rational experience.
Explaining the individual
Pick a significant individual phenomena from history e.g., an invention, an achievement, a stance; develop a sequential narrative that would eventually produce as its consequence this aforementioned result. Try to include as many factors as possible, including but not limited to sociological, economic, political and cultural determinants. Try to leave no gap in the chain of events. What would it take to offer a complete causal explanation? What would it take to offer a sufficient causal explanation?
Individual and history
This theoretical work of inquiring into necessary conditions for possible experience did not reach its conclusion with the exploration of mental categories of rationality. Following Immanuel Kant, G. W. F. Hegel introduced a larger context, namely, history into the picture. Hegel pointed towards history as the prerequisite for any individual experience. Hegel’s method differed from Kant, in that he found the subject not in a static position of reflection but in a wild movement composed of flux of constant thinking subject animated by dramatic encounters with limitations, negations and appropriations (Hegel, 1807/1977). For instance, in the movement of thinking, the subject recognizes its thinking activity through the awareness of the medium of thinking, namely, language in its objectivity. In realizing this medium as an instrument of communication, the subject recognizes the alterity that imbues this objectivity from its self. With this realization, the identification of subject, language and thinking is shattered and gives way to cracks of alienation of subject from itself through which lights of history fall within the interiority of subjectivity. One speaks another’s language (Fanon, 2008).
Then, the self is not an autonomous entity but a dependent one. The subject is not self-constituted but becomes a thinking being through what’s offered by another. Language is not the product of one’s thinking but conversely, one’s own thinking is the product of someone else’s language. We do not speak language, but language speaks us! In facing its late arrival to the scene of experience, the individual recognizes historical time as the condition of subjective time. Through this process, thinking is discovered to be not only a matter of understanding but an act. By thinking through language, one acts (self changes through its awareness of what makes her up), and is acted upon.
Not only, as the primary product of its thinking essence, subject’s words are discovered to be a part of a negotiated reality (Gramsci, 1971), but also the very freedom of activity that defines subject’s moral character that allow subject to decide on what’s right and what’s wrong is contingent upon a struggle onto death with other individuals who possesses this freedom and the ability to set moral criteria to guide behavior (Hegel, 1977, pp. 104-119).
Truly free exercise of reason requires that the subject recognizes no limits to its rational process. Yet in following its course, the subject encounters another who is at work in a similar way, realizing its own rational potential through the execution of free choices. In this encounter, both become the limit of the other. Hegel goes on to argue that it is true this facing of another’s potential freedom, the true meaning of freedom is actualized as struggle-onto-death as the ultimate limit of one’s own ability to act freely. The consequence of this implicit story behind social interactions determines one’s hierarchical standing.
As a summary statement of all the social forces that one chooses to submit instead of ‘fight to death’, with its freedom and for its freedom, Hegel’s elaboration on the critical philosophy of Kant, transformed critical philosophy into critical social theory. What do we accept as necessary to survive? What material forces determine this acceptance? To what extent do ideas play a role in our perception of what’s necessary for survival? And how do we define the minimal conditions of survival?
Dependence and Independence
- Let’s imagine a hierarchical dynamic between two entities. Scales can be varied. Either parents and their child, State and its citizens, or Advanced colonial state and underdeveloped country with its nascent productive economy. Describe structures of dependency. What claims to independence can be proposed and realized and at what cost?
- In countering idealization of autonomy, insofar as it’s a value unavailable to certain social strata, social theorists propose relationality as a mode to theorize social interactions. Under what conditions stronger bonds of dependency can function as a better political solution compared to cultivation of independence?
Individual and work
Existing in a body, existing through a body, the thinking subject is predicated upon bodily subsistence. Thrown outside of its discursive flow into its material, sensuous and energetic engagement with its environment, the individual is then placed within conditions necessary for such subsistence. This is called work. Critique of the individual paves the way for the analysis of the social organization of work (Marx & Engels, 1970). By analyzing the division of labor, surplus production, accumulation, private property and exploitation, an individual’s differentiation into historically irreducible class positions is laid bare.
Exercise: The study of paradigmatic examples through research and artworks
Individual’s work, its conditions and novelty
Martin Luther (1953) Director: Irving Pichel, Writers: Allan Sloane, Lothar Wolff
At the end of each chapter, we will analyze historical and fictional examples in order to illustrate and also to deepen the chapter’s points.
For this chapter on the political sociological problematic of the individual, research the life of 16th century German priest Martin Luther and/or watch the film “Martin Luther” that fictionalizes his life. What political sociological analysis can be developed around this individual? Here are some dimensions that lend themselves to a rich analysis of this question.
- Luther criticized and protested the Church as a believer and thereby risked excommunication.
- How can Luther’s engagement with the doctrines of the church be understood in relation to Durkheim’s notion of externality and the coerciveness of social facts? How can his practice be used as a paradigmatic example of problems of Durkheim’s sociology?
- How can Luther be understood both as an expression of social norm “true Christian” and as an abnormality as a “heretic”? What conceptualization of the individual can account for his transformative position that both accepts and rejects authorized discourses?
- What’s the relationship between the individual and the technology of their time as expressed in the life/film of Martin Luther?
- In the histories of modernity, the development of the printing press is often shown as a major technological force driving growing literacy, thereby critical skills of the larger populations.
- Discuss technological determinism in conjunction with the concept of ‘event analysis’ whereby only a constellation of factors come to explain large-scale transformation. How’s Luther’s intense, personal, spiritual and political debates through 95 theses and his dissertations actualize potentiality of printing press?
- What’s the role of the geopolitical system and nascent international order in giving Martin Luther space to translate the Bible into German? Luther reflects on the religious practice of selling of indulgences and finds them problematic and in contradiction with other spiritual principles such as sola fide (only faith), sola scriptura (only text), and sola Gracie (only grace). In doing so, he faces backlash from the Church that organizes not only religious life but also political life by (de)sanctifying/(de)legitimizing political authority. How can we reconcile the work of the individual (Luther’s personal crisis of faith, individual efforts to develop his thinking, and personal work of translating the sacred text) with the socio-political conditions of his time? The same conditions did not produce a similar individual. Yet Luther perhaps would not be able to accomplish his goals without the political struggles among the princedoms and the Church.
- The questions of historicity. Following the footsteps of St Augustine (397-400/2006), Luther’s life demonstrates the importance of interiority, where a personal space becomes the womb of an idea, which then becomes a project intermixed with its context and interdependent on a network of socio-material relations.
- The idea ofthe individual develops and materializes with a specific historicity. Its development carries the mark of the Christian concept of soul that animates the body and represents what’s believed to be the divine connection of humans to God. In time, the religious conception of the soul will give way to a more secular notion of the mind. Yet, both the religious doctrine of soul and Cartesian philosophy, the category of individual operates within the opposition of mind to body. What underpins the individuality in the latter is the activity of thinking.
- This conception will later pave the way of one of the founding principles of modern political culture, namely, the freedom of expression. Related to freedom of expression are freedom of conscience and freedom of thought. With the articulation of the personality of thought, there is a movement from the divine origin of knowledge to the sanctity of personal freedom of thought. The proliferation of culture, political ideologies, and civil liberties are conditioned upon the fracture induced on the wall of collective dogma.
- Martin Luther’s life bears witness to the sovereignty of the state in encapsulating individual freedom of thought. As Luther’s history shows; philosophies, religious faiths and personal opinions find the room and light to flourish and get their seal of approval only in the context of adequate supportive political power. Then, there is a double dependency between 1) ongoing characterization of founding principles of culture through work (in science, art, religion, philosophy) and 2) political protection of space of creativity. There tension will be the stage of modern political dramas whereby question of freedom will be posed in conjunction with question of security.
Branching out through further reading
In this section, we will offer paths outside themes, terms and problematics explored throughout the chapter. These works are opportunities for personalizing the study of political sociology as well as directions for research. The relation of recommended works to the chapter is multivalent, ranging from critical elaborations of the central ideas into illustrative expansions of research inquiries. Exposure to this work will lay bare the ungeneralizable transdisciplinarity of political sociology. There is an inexhaustible series of disciplines, cultures and events from which political sociological research emerges. By branching out, we shall break new fronts and discover the fuzzy and heterogeneous beginnings of fundamental inquiry.
1. Three Theban Plays: Antigone, Oedipus the King, Oedipus at Colonus; Sophocles
Engaging Oedipal blindness
Readers are also invited to explore the tension between familial authority and political authority. How is the separation of personal and political proposed and contested? Does the play, Oedipus the King, offer a solution to the problems it’s raising? If not, what’s the value of tragic experience?
In the story of Antigone, the daughter of Oedipus, political theory found its paradigmatic scene of resistance. Antigone refuses the injunction of the King, which forbids the burial ritual for her brother. A listless, unrelenting, and outspoken Antigone goes ahead and completes the necessary funerary steps demanded by the custom. This defiant act is punished by King Creon with Antigone’s burial while she is alive. In this powerful, tragic unfolding, one of the founding stories of conflict between family and state, the limits of political power, the possibility of cultural transformation, and the questions of divided loyalty are posed.
2. Antigone’s Claim: Kinship Between Life and Death, Judith Butler
Aberrant itinaries
Readers are invited to attend to the introduction of a new axis of thinking into a well-throdden terrain. How does Butler further politicize this artistic document and the tradition that formed around it that has already played a foundational role for political theory?
3. The Category of the Person: Anthropology, Philosophy, History; Editors Michael Carrithers, Steven Collins, Steven Lukes
This book is offered for further study of the political status of the notion of the individual. It is an edited volume which, as an academic genre, functions to document the current state of the literature or make available to the public the works presented at a conference or colloquium. Marcel Mauss’s ethnographic reflections on the historical development of the category of person constitutes the main work around which contemporary scholars offer their contributions. Layers of historical experience are coded into the modern, at times naturalized sense of the individual. Anthropological and philosophical inquiry lay bare entanglements of the category that makes it impossible to see it as mere flatting out social complexity or reduction of the sociopolitical affordance of the notion to the Bourgeois individualism of the 19th century.
Practice of scholarship
4. Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks, Friedrich Nietzsche
In this series of written lectures, philologist Friedrich Nietzsche discusses the co-emergence of philosophy and the philosopher. The individual is their philosophy. The individual thought of each philosopher represents a new way of grasping the essence of being. This contemplative attitude combined with articulation in language built true reasons, propositions and arguments will constitute an alternative to the mythological representation of reality based on anonymous or divine sources. Interrogated, examined, and digested knowledge will be defended against given wisdom. In this book, Nietzsche analyzes so-called pre-Socratic philosophers. This periodization has critical importance in the history of thought. In his lectures on aesthetics, Hegel argues, having analyzed Antigone as the highest example of tragic play, continues with the life of Socrates, the philosopher seen by most as the first sacrifice of democratic community, the first causality of free exercise of thought. Socrates will elevate rational argumentation in public to an art form through these conversations that lay bare the unexamined assumptions of his interlocutors. In this performativity, he will actively engage in the dramatic character of theoretical inquiry. Yet, Nietzsche in his philosophic work will find a fundamental turning point in the nascent philosophic journey, as outward appearance will be increasingly contrasted with abstract forms and the spirit of appreciating the tragic beauty will be replaced by first ironic reflections of Plato and then later by encyclopedic research of Aristotle.
Beginnings
- Philosophers from Thales onward debated one another’s premises while also reaching new ideas as a result of these preceding examinations. With each individual philosophy, Nietzsche emphasizes a new step towards differentiation and perhaps a new beginning.
- Readers are invited to reflect on the generative character of philosophical conversation. Across locals and across years, philosophers are responding to another thought, and thereby inducing a new type of relation among humans. Individuals are not assimilated into an anonymous figure of society. Generators of ideas are not hidden behind divine masks.
- To what extent open debate is universal to the concept of political life?
- What are the conditions of possibility of limitless philosophic inquiry? Should there be limits to philosophy?
- How can the political community stay aware of its limitations? What are the current modes of ‘theater’ and ‘philosophy’ you see playing this role of showing the essential and the aberrant?
Works Cited
Augustine, S. (2006). Confessions (H. Chadwick, Trans.). Oxford University Press. (Original work written c. 397–400)
Butler, J. (2000). Antigone’s claim: Kinship between life and death. Columbia University Press.
Carrithers, M., Collins, S., & Lukes, S. (Eds.). (1985). The category of the person: Anthropology, philosophy, history. Cambridge University Press.
Durkheim, É. (1982). What is a social fact? In S. Lukes (Ed.), The rules of sociological method (W. D. Halls, Trans., pp. 50–59). Free Press. (Original work published 1895)
Durkheim, É. (1997). The division of labor in society (W. D. Halls, Trans.). Free Press. (Original work published 1893)
Durkheim, É. (2005). Suicide: A study in sociology (J. A. Spaulding & G. Simpson, Trans.). Routledge. (Original work published 1897)
Fanon, F. (2008). Black skin, white masks (R. Philcox, Trans.). Grove Press. (Original work published 1952)
Goffman, E. (1959). The presentation of self in everyday life. Anchor Books.
Goffman, E. (1963). Stigma: Notes on the management of spoiled identity. Prentice-Hall.
Gramsci, A. (1971). Selections from the prison notebooks (Q. Hoare & G. N. Smith, Eds. & Trans.). International Publishers.
Foucault, M. (2003). Abnormal: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1974–1975 (V. Marchetti & A. Salomoni, Eds.; G. Burchell, Trans.). Picador.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1977). Phenomenology of spirit (A. V. Miller, Trans.). Oxford University Press. (Original work published 1807)
Kant, I. (1998). Critique of pure reason (P. Guyer & A. W. Wood, Trans. & Eds.). Cambridge University Press. (Original work published 1781)
Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1970). The German ideology (C. J. Arthur, Ed.). International Publishers. (Original work written 1846)
Nietzsche, F. (1998). Philosophy in the tragic age of the Greeks (M. Faber, Trans.). Prometheus Books. (Original work published 1873)
Sophocles. (2002). The three Theban plays: Antigone; Oedipus the king; Oedipus at Colonus (R. Fagles, Trans.). Penguin Classics.
1) production of usefulness. 2) product of labor. 3) unit through which to understand historicity of society.
controversial certified papers allowing forgiveness in medieval Christian practice
Related to the philosophy of Rene Descartes
Throwing light on something, bringing something to visibility. Greek metaphysical principle that binds together seeing and knowing. Commented most prominently by philosopher Martin Heidegger.
nonnormative, heterodox disposition.